Show simple item record

dc.contributor.advisorAlex Byrne.en_US
dc.contributor.authorBalcarras, David Alexander.en_US
dc.contributor.otherMassachusetts Institute of Technology. Department of Linguistics and Philosophy.en_US
dc.date.accessioned2021-01-06T17:41:29Z
dc.date.available2021-01-06T17:41:29Z
dc.date.copyright2020en_US
dc.date.issued2020en_US
dc.identifier.urihttps://hdl.handle.net/1721.1/129124
dc.descriptionThesis: Ph. D. in Linguistics, Massachusetts Institute of Technology, Department of Linguistics and Philosophy, September, 2020en_US
dc.descriptionCataloged from student-submitted PDF version of thesis.en_US
dc.descriptionIncludes bibliographical references (pages 169-185).en_US
dc.description.abstractWhat is language? I defend the view that language is the practical capacity for partaking in communication with linguistic signs. To have a language just is to know how to communicate with it. I argue that this view -- communicationism --en_US
dc.description.abstractis compatible with its main rival: the view that we know our language by tacitly knowing a particular generative grammar, a set of rules and principles pairing sounds with meanings. But only communicationism gets at language's essence. Moreover, the rival view may be false, for there is in fact little reason to think we tacitly know grammars. In chapter 1, I argue that communicationism is compatible with the view that language is constituted by tacit knowledge of grammar because the brain states that realize grammatical knowledge do so because they enable us to know how to linguistically communicate. In chapter 2, I offer further reasons to accept communicationism. The starting thought that we know how to communicate by knowing how to use sentences in a particular rule-governed way in order to express our thoughts is developed into a use-based account of meaning, on which all expressions have their meanings because we know how we use them to mean things.en_US
dc.description.abstractIn chapter 3, I explore the extent to which language use is enabled by unconscious representations of grammatical rules. In particular, I consider whether linguistic understanding is enabled by tacit knowledge of compositional semantics. I argue that it is not. Language comprehension and production can be explained without appeal to tacit knowledge of semantics, by instead appealing to our subpersonal capacity to translate natural language sentences into the medium of thought. I conclude that there does not seem to be any reason to believe in tacit knowledge of grammar. Finally, in chapter 4, I survey proposals about what it would be for a speaker to tacitly know a grammar, and argue that they are all inadequate. I conclude that linguistic meaning cannot be explained in terms of tacit knowledge of grammar. Rather, it should be understood in terms of the practical knowledge that manifests in intentional linguistic action, rather than in terms of that which might underlie it.en_US
dc.description.statementofresponsibilityby David Alexander Balcarras.en_US
dc.format.extent185 pagesen_US
dc.language.isoengen_US
dc.publisherMassachusetts Institute of Technologyen_US
dc.rightsMIT theses may be protected by copyright. Please reuse MIT thesis content according to the MIT Libraries Permissions Policy, which is available through the URL provided.en_US
dc.rights.urihttp://dspace.mit.edu/handle/1721.1/7582en_US
dc.subjectLinguistics and Philosophy.en_US
dc.titleOn what language isen_US
dc.typeThesisen_US
dc.description.degreePh. D. in Linguisticsen_US
dc.contributor.departmentMassachusetts Institute of Technology. Department of Linguistics and Philosophyen_US
dc.identifier.oclc1227180204en_US
dc.description.collectionPh.D.inLinguistics Massachusetts Institute of Technology, Department of Linguistics and Philosophyen_US
dspace.imported2021-01-06T17:41:28Zen_US
mit.thesis.degreeDoctoralen_US
mit.thesis.departmentLingen_US


Files in this item

Thumbnail

This item appears in the following Collection(s)

Show simple item record