dc.contributor.advisor | David Pesetsky | |
dc.contributor.author | Newman, Elise Sophia Bershad | |
dc.date.accessioned | 2022-02-07T15:24:12Z | |
dc.date.available | 2022-02-07T15:24:12Z | |
dc.date.issued | 2021-09 | |
dc.date.submitted | 2021-09-29T17:20:27.484Z | |
dc.identifier.uri | https://hdl.handle.net/1721.1/140102 | |
dc.description.abstract | This thesis asks the following question: what can wh-movement teach us about verb phrase structure? I examine two apparent interactions between wh-movement and Voice: Mayan Agent Focus and the Double Object Movement Asymmetry (DOMA) (Holmberg et al., 2019). In certain Mayan languages, subject but not object wh-questions require the verb to take a special intransitive-looking form; in many languages with symmetrical passives, wh-moving an indirect object in a passive clause is restricted to contexts in which the indirect object is the passive subject. By contrast, wh-moving direct objects face no restrictions about which argument is the passive subject. Typical approaches to these phenomena take the basic underlying verb phrase structure of a language to be insensitive to whether any of its arguments are wh-phrases. In other words, the fact that wh-questions are built from clauses containing a wh-element, while non-questions are built from clauses that lack a wh-element, is assumed to be irrelevant to what we assume the basic underlying clause structure to be in each case — object wh-questions are therefore assumed to be built from clauses that are identical to their non-wh-counterparts; subject wh-questions are assumed to built form clauses that are identical to their non-wh-counterparts, and so forth. On this view, many researchers propose that the so-called interactions between wh-movement and Voice should be explained by constraints on wh-movement from certain contexts. By contrast, I take the opposite approach. I propose that the observed interactions between wh-movement and Voice are teaching us very transparently about the basic structure of clauses that contain wh-elements, which may be different than their non-wh-counterparts. In other words, Mayan Agent Focus teaches us that clauses containing a wh-subject (as opposed to a non-wh-subject) are built in such a way as to feed intransitive-looking morphosyntax; the DOMA is teaching us that indirect object wh-phrases (in contrast to non-wh-indirect objects) are always generated in such a way as to make them the subject in a passive clause. I propose a theory of the features driving Merge in which the underlying position of a wh-phrase is not only determined by the “selectional” properties of verbs, but also by the feature that controls successive cyclic wh-movement through the edge of the verbal domain. Thus, the structure of a verb phrase is not invariant across all contexts — it depends on the features and categories of the elements that are configured inside of it, including the distribution of wh-elements. This approach likewise has implications for clauses that do not contain wh-elements, which I propose account for symmetric and asymmetric A and A-movement in different contexts. | |
dc.publisher | Massachusetts Institute of Technology | |
dc.rights | In Copyright - Educational Use Permitted | |
dc.rights | Copyright MIT | |
dc.rights.uri | http://rightsstatements.org/page/InC-EDU/1.0/ | |
dc.title | The (in)distinction between wh-movement and c-selection | |
dc.type | Thesis | |
dc.description.degree | Ph.D. | |
dc.contributor.department | Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Department of Linguistics and Philosophy | |
dc.identifier.orcid | https://orcid.org/0000-0001-7154-6922 | |
mit.thesis.degree | Doctoral | |
thesis.degree.name | Doctor of Philosophy | |