Show simple item record

dc.contributor.advisorStephen Yablo.en_US
dc.contributor.authorPhillips-Brown, Milo.en_US
dc.contributor.otherMassachusetts Institute of Technology. Department of Linguistics and Philosophy.en_US
dc.date.accessioned2020-03-09T18:53:11Z
dc.date.available2020-03-09T18:53:11Z
dc.date.copyright2019en_US
dc.date.issued2019en_US
dc.identifier.urihttps://hdl.handle.net/1721.1/124093
dc.descriptionThesis: Ph. D. in Linguistics, Massachusetts Institute of Technology, Department of Linguistics and Philosophy, 2019en_US
dc.descriptionCataloged from PDF version of thesis.en_US
dc.descriptionIncludes bibliographical references (pages 77-82).en_US
dc.description.abstractWanting is an easy concept to use. Talk to any three year-old and you'll know they've mastered it. Wanting is important, too. We understand one another in no small part through what they want, and wanting is a pillar in theories of mind and ethics. An account of wanting, then, must do dual duties: be powerful enough to carry this theoretical burden and simple enough to explain wanting's effortless use in daily life. The first two Chapters of this dissertation discharge these duties in part. The latter two Chapters complicate the task of discharging them further. Chapter 1. Folk psychology and decision theory both represent our belieflike and desire- and preference-like states. Both use these representations to explain and predict our actions. If we can't account for one in terms of the other, we'd have a dubious dualism-two competing systems of representation, prediction, and explanation. I give a decision-theoretic account of a key folk psychological notion-wanting.en_US
dc.description.abstractChapter 2. What we want depends on what we believe. Yet you can want to stay home (it would be nice to) despite believing it would ruin your career. This case confounds my theory from Chapter 1, as well as the orthodox semantics for 'want'. In Chapter 2, I develop a semantics based idea that you want to stay home considering its benefits, but ignoring the career consequences. Chapter 3. The meaning of anankastic conditionals-like 'if you want to go to Harlem, you have to take the A train'-is clear, yet how it arises compositionally has proven an enigma. Many had thought the enigma unraveled by Condoravdi and Lauer (2016). I argue not: anankastic conditionals are still a mystery. Chapter 4 (co-authored with Lyndal Grant).en_US
dc.description.abstractThe widely held Satisfactionis- Truth Principle-if A wants p, then A has a desire that is satisfied in exactly the worlds where p is true-posits an appealingly straightforward link between what we want and the satisfaction conditions of our desires, and in turn, enables appealingly straightforward accounts linking what we want, the wanting relation, and the contents of desires. We argue that the principle is nonetheless false.en_US
dc.description.statementofresponsibilityby Milo Phillips-Brown.en_US
dc.format.extent82 pagesen_US
dc.language.isoengen_US
dc.publisherMassachusetts Institute of Technologyen_US
dc.rightsMIT theses are protected by copyright. They may be viewed, downloaded, or printed from this source but further reproduction or distribution in any format is prohibited without written permission.en_US
dc.rights.urihttp://dspace.mit.edu/handle/1721.1/7582en_US
dc.subjectLinguistics and Philosophy.en_US
dc.titleWhat it means to wanten_US
dc.typeThesisen_US
dc.description.degreePh. D. in Linguisticsen_US
dc.contributor.departmentMassachusetts Institute of Technology. Department of Linguistics and Philosophyen_US
dc.identifier.oclc1142632800en_US
dc.description.collectionPh.D.inLinguistics Massachusetts Institute of Technology, Department of Linguistics and Philosophyen_US
dspace.imported2020-03-09T18:53:10Zen_US
mit.thesis.degreeDoctoralen_US
mit.thesis.departmentLingen_US


Files in this item

Thumbnail

This item appears in the following Collection(s)

Show simple item record