dc.contributor.author | Skow, Bradford | |
dc.date.accessioned | 2011-03-18T16:16:09Z | |
dc.date.available | 2011-03-18T16:16:09Z | |
dc.date.issued | 2011-01 | |
dc.identifier.issn | 1468-0068 | |
dc.identifier.uri | http://hdl.handle.net/1721.1/61727 | |
dc.description.abstract | According to the moving spotlight theory of time, the property of being present
moves from earlier times to later times, like a spotlight shone on spacetime by God.
In more detail, the theory has three components. First, it is a version of eternalism:
all times, past present and future, exist. (Here I use “exist” in its tenseless sense.)
Second, it is a version of the A-theory of time: there are non-relative facts about
which times are past, which time is present, and which times are future. That is,
it is not just that the year 1066 is past relative to 2007. The year 1066 is also past
full-stop, not relative to any other time. (The A-theory is opposed to the B-theory
of time, which says that facts about which times are past obtain only relative to
other times.) And third, on this view the passage of time is a real phenomenon.
Which moment is present keeps changing. As I will sometimes put it, the NOW
moves from the past toward the future. And this does not mean that relative to
di erent times, di erent times are present. Even the B-theory can say that 1999 is
present relative to 1999 but is not present relative to 2007. No, according to the
moving spotlight theory, the claim that which moment is present keeps changing is
supposed to be true, even from a perspective outside time. My main goal in this paper is to present a new version of the moving spotlight
theory (though in some respects the theory I present also resembles the growing
block universe theory of time). This version makes a connection between the
passage of time (the motion of the NOW) and change. In fact, it uses facts about
change to explain facts about the passage of time. The bulk of the paper is devoted
to describing, in detail, how the theory works. I also believe that my new version
has advantages over the standard version. It explains things that the standard version
cannot explain. It explains both why the NOW moves, and why it moves at a
constant rate. I will discuss why I think these are advantages in the final section. | en_US |
dc.language.iso | en_US | |
dc.publisher | Wiley | en_US |
dc.relation.isversionof | http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-0068.2010.00784.x | en_US |
dc.rights | Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-Share Alike 3.0 | en_US |
dc.rights.uri | http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-sa/3.0/ | en_US |
dc.source | MIT web domain | en_US |
dc.title | Why Does Time Pass? | en_US |
dc.type | Article | en_US |
dc.identifier.citation | Skow, Bradford. “Why Does Time Pass?.” Noûs (2010): no. doi: 10.1111/j.1468-0068.2010.00784.x © 2011 Wiley | en_US |
dc.contributor.department | Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Department of Linguistics and Philosophy | en_US |
dc.contributor.approver | Skow, Bradford | |
dc.contributor.mitauthor | Skow, Bradford | |
dc.relation.journal | Noûs | en_US |
dc.eprint.version | Author's final manuscript | en_US |
dc.type.uri | http://purl.org/eprint/type/JournalArticle | en_US |
eprint.status | http://purl.org/eprint/status/PeerReviewed | en_US |
dspace.orderedauthors | Skow, Bradford | en |
dc.identifier.orcid | https://orcid.org/0000-0002-7892-4540 | |
mit.license | OPEN_ACCESS_POLICY | en_US |
mit.metadata.status | Complete | |